Here is part one of the paper. Bibliography will appear at the end of each part for reference.
The
Evolving Just War Tradition: Lessons Learned From Iraq
The
relationship of Christianity to violence has had a long and bountiful
history – both through the fruits of academic discourse and through
the spoils and suffering of “holy war.” The tradition of
arguments for the justified use of deadly force has come to be known
as Just War Theory – although many modern theorists prefer to
replace “theory” with “tradition” to more accurately reflect
the genealogy and ongoing revision of its arguments. Since Augustine,
this tradition has passed through Thomas Aquinas, Martin Luther, and
the Anabaptists all the way to contemporary Christian ethicists such
as Reinhold Niebuhr and John Howard Yoder.
While it
is not the goal of this paper to provide a historical or theoretical
review of the Just War tradition, it will be necessary to establish
the most common criteria used in arguing for the justified use of
force. I will then examine the Just War critiques for the 2003
invasion of Iraq (hereafter referred to as the “Iraq War”) and
see if there are any commonalities among these critiques – the vast
majority of which find the Iraq War to be unjustified. Using these
commonalities, I will attempt to offer reasons for the failure of the
tradition to prevent this war. These reasons can be used in an
attempt to better critique any future conflicts that may arise. While
the Just War tradition may not ever result in a lasting global peace,
I believe the goal of making each successive war more just than the
last would go a long way towards reducing the amount of suffering
inherent in war.
Criteria
Justifying the Use of Force
The
criteria that the Just War tradition addresses most commonly fall
into two separate categories: jus ad bellum
which establishes what just causes for war might be (pre-war
criteria) and jus in bello
which provide criteria for justly prosecuting a war (in-war
criteria). Yoder has assembled a 13 page list of all the various
criteria historically mentioned as necessary for a just war. The goal
of this list is to show the magnitude and evolution of the tradition
(Yoder 147-161). While this appendix is insightful, a more concise
framework for justifiable violence is outlined by A. James Reimer in
Christians and War.
This framework is also found in the vast majority of Just War
thinkers in some way or another. Reimer boils down jus ad
bellum criteria to:
(1) legitimate authority declaring and waging war; (2) just cause;
(3) peace as the ultimate intention or goal; (4) love of neighbor.
not hatred or vengefulness, as the motivation; (5) war as last
resort – all other avenues must have been exhausted before going to
war; and (6) probability of success. (73)
To
these six criteria are added four more that cover jus in
bello:
(7) means as commensurate with the intended end; (8) proportionality
of means to end – the harm caused must not exceed the harm
prevented; (9) immunity of innocent people – the distinction
between combatants and noncombatants; and (10) respect for
international law. (Reimer 73-4)
Reimer's ten criteria provide a broad yet manageable foundation for
understanding the framework within which the Christian tradition
views the justification of violence. To this religious framework,
Michael Walzer adds a secular utilitarian view. While Walzer agrees
with all of the criteria outlined above, he also relies on the
“domestic analogy” and number crunching as the basis for many of
his criteria. For Walzer, “every comparison of home and country or
of personal property and political independence” relies on this
analogy (58). In this view, just war is like killing an intruder and
aggressive invasion is like breaking and entering. Where he admits
this analogy fails, however, is that there are no police to call on
when one country is charged with breaking and entering. Because of
this, Walzer argues that “police powers are distributed among all
the members [of international society]” (59). From this, Walzer
lays out criteria for determining the aggressor in a conflict
(similar to Reimer's six pre-war criteria) and calls for a response.
A unilateral response is only just when the sole reacting party is
the one being attacked. In many modern cases, the attacked is for all
practical reasons defenseless. In these cases, Walzer argues that a
multilateral response is the only just response. Third parties acting
unilaterally will most often betray some level of self-interest
(here, Walzer's secular philosophy matches very nicely with Reinhold
Niebuhr's Christian realism). While this self-interest may also be
the case in multilateral actions, its dilution is a lesser of two
evils (Walzer xiv).
Before
advancing to the intricacies of the justification for the Iraq War,
it should be pointed out that pacifism is also a strong Christian
tradition regarding violence. Some Christian pacifists take their
inspiration from the Decalog, but most focus on the Sermon on the
Mount. The Society of Friends (the Quakers) are probably the most
well known pacifists while other Anabaptists, such as the Mennonites,
also represent the peace movement. Both Yoder and Reimer are
Mennonite pacifists. Interestingly enough, both have written books on
Just War. Yoder's When War Is Unjust
is an excellent accompaniment to Walzer. While often agreeing with
Walzer, Yoder raises two important points that deserve mention.
First, the Just War ethic must
at times serve the negative function of denouncing a war or possible
war as unjust. Yoder seems to be aiming mainly at government
officials and Christian spokespeople who run in those powerful
circles. The calls for jus in bello
during World War II from Christian ethicists as well as the
denouncement of the Vietnam War by similar voices point to an
overgeneralization by Yoder. There have been Christian denouncements
of unjust wars and unjust means, but they are often unsuccessful. Yet
Yoder is correct in accenting the negative quality of the tradition –
some wars are simply not just.
The second point that Yoder makes is the necessity for selective
conscientious objection. Pacifism teaches that all wars are immoral.
This makes it easy for a pacifist to claim conscientious objection.
An individual who subscribes to the Just War tradition, however, will
refuse to fight only in unjust wars. Yet this action could land that
individual in jail. As Yoder states:
The fact that a Quaker or Amish young man, rejecting all wars as his
church teaches, could be recognized as a conscientious objector and
given alternative service, whereas a Catholic or Lutheran draftee,
evaluating wars case by case as his church teaches, could not,
represents a kind of backhanded establishment of religion. (49)
Yoder is right, I believe, in hinting at the unconstitutionality of
the lack of selective conscientious objection. If one's religion
teaches them to practice moral discernment as outlined in the Just
War tradition, prohibiting that person from practicing this aspect of
their faith could not only be seen as a “backhanded establishment
of religion” but also as a violation of one's freedom of religion.1
While the pacifist tradition is strong in this country, I believe
that both Yoder's and Reimer's decision to address Just War tradition
acknowledges the pragmatic necessity of accepting that we will not
see “peace in our time” but must rather work on restraining war.
It is here that I believe the majority of American Christians would
agree with Reinhold Niebuhr who, when writing in April 1941 about the
precarious state of Europe, says “the only peace that Hitler would
accept now would be one that left an unredeemed continent under the
heel of his dictatorship and that would give him the possibility of a
more complete triumph later” (172). For Niebuhr and many
Christians, an unjust peace is not preferable to a just war.
PART 2 FOUND HERE.
PART 2 FOUND HERE.
1The
case for selective conscientious objection is most valid regarding
conscription, but possibly could also be applicable to enlistment.
Bibliography
Burghardt,
Walter J. “A Just War? In Iraq?” Living Pulpit 14.4
(2005): 18-19. PDF.
Calabrese,
Andrew. "Casus
Belli:
U.S. Media and the Justification of the Iraq
War."
Television
& New Media 6.2
(2005): 153-175.
PDF.
Casey,
Shaun. “Just War and Iraq? Ethical Theory Says No.” Word &
World 23.1 (2003): 94-96. PDF.
Colson,
Charles. “Just War in Iraq: Sometimes Going to War Is the
Charitable Thing to Do.” Christianity Today
46.13 (2002): 72. PDF.
Fredrickson,
David. “Pauline Ethics: Congregations as Communities of Moral
Deliberation.”
The
Promise of Lutheran Ethics. Ed.
Karen Bloomquist and John R. Stumme.
Minneapolis:
Fortress P, 1998. 115-129. Print.
Gorringe, Timothy.
"The Case for a Pre-emptive Strike, and So Forth.."
Political Theology 5.2 (2004): 215-218. PDF.
Gumucio,
Cristián Parker. "War and Armed Conflicts: The Ambivalent Role
of the Communications Media.” Return
of the Just War.
24-32. London: SCM Pr, 2001. PDF.
Himes,
Kenneth. “Intervention, Just War, and U.S. National Security.”
Theological Studies 65
(2004): 141-157.
PDF.
Lull,
Patricia. “Just War and Iraq? Ethical Action Requires
Conversation.” Word & World 23.1
(2003): 95-97. PDF.
Maguire, Daniel.
“The Abnormality of War: Dissecting the 'Just War' Euphemisms and
Building an Ethics of Peace.” Horizons 33.1 (2006):
111-126. PDF.
McCormick, Patrick
T. “Saving 'Citizen' Ryan: Supporting a Just War or Just Supporting
the
Troops?.” Journal
of the Society of Christian Ethics 29.1 (2009): 109-126. PDF.
Niebuhr,
Reinhold. Love and Justice: Selections from the Shorter Writings
of Reinhold Niebuhr.
Philadelphia: The
Westminster P, 1957. Print.
Reimer, A. James.
Christians and War. Minneapolis: Fortress P: 2010. Print.
Revering, Alan. "The
Injustice of Some Attacks: A Response to Stephen Strehle."
Political Theology 5.3 (2004): 350-360. PDF.
Riswold, Caryn. “A
Theological Response to 'The Case for a Pre-emptive Strike.'”
Political
Theology 5.2
(2004): 201-213. PDF.
Robinson, Paul,
Nigel de Lee, Don Carrick. Ethics Education in the Military.
Cornwall: Ashgate,
2008. Print.
Robinson,
Piers, et al. "Testing Models of Media Performance in Wartime:
U.K. TV News and the 2003 Invasion
of Iraq."
Journal
of Communication 59.3
(2009): 534-563. PDF.
Stiltner, Brian.
“Just War: Second Thoughts on Iraq.” Christian Century 12
Dec 2006: 34-35. PDF.
Strehle, Stephen.
"Dead Hookers and Las Vegas: A Response to the Critics of My
Article on the War in Iraq." Political Theology 5.3
(2004): 361-374. PDF.
Strehle, Stephen.
"Saddam Hussein, Islam, and Just War Theory: The Case for a
Pre-emptive Strike." Political Theology 5.1 (2004):
76-101. PDF.
Taylor,
Ian. "Surveying the Battlefield: Mapping the Different Arguments
and Positions of the Iraq War Debate Through Frame
Analysis."
Westminster
Papers in Communication & Culture 5.3
(2008): 69-90. PDF.
Walzer,
Michael. Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with
Historical Illustrations. 3rd
ed.
Basic Books, 2000.
Print.
Weigel, George.
“Just War and Iraq Wars.” First Things 172 (2007): 14-20.
PDF.
Yoder, John H. When
War is Unjust: Being Honest in Just-War Thinking. 2nd
ed. Eugene: Wipf &
Stock,
2001. Print.
No comments:
Post a Comment